Skinner
Skinner, B. F.
Behaviourism
Behaviourism was a highly influential school of psychology founded by JB Watson in the early part of the twentieth century (though with earlier roots in the work of Thorndike and Pavlov). Its primary feature was a rejection of many methods used by psychologists up to that date, in particular the value of 'introspection': the idea that psychologists could gain useful insights by looking within their own minds. As explored by Wilhelm Wundt and his followers, introspection led to serious problems of reliability and validity, with disagreements among observers who were reporting responses to the same stimulus. Watson's solution to this methodological impasse was radical – he proposed that if psychology was to be properly 'scientific' (in the manner of the natural sciences, such as physics, chemistry and biology) then it must reject the study of mental events entirely, and confine itself to the study of externally observable behaviour (hence the name behaviourism). The basic idea was that behaviour can be understood entirely without reference to the concept of mind or consciousness, simply by looking at connections between the stimuli applied to a particular organism, and the resulting responses. Behaviourism's insistence on rigorous scientific methodology is still influential in many fields of psychology today, even though its original denial of mental representations has been largely discarded.\nAnother feature of Watson's approach was to look for parallels between humans and other animals in terms of common features involved in learning processes. In particular, the laboratory rat occupied pride of place in many a psychological laboratory, providing insight into issues such as conditioning and reinforcement. Another key aspect of Watson's critique was on the previous importance given by many psychologists to 'innate' factors (i.e. those present at birth, governing behaviour by instinct rather than through learning of some kind). While Watson did not deny the existence of such aspects (suggesting that learning builds on innate factors), he argued that innate factors had been overemphasized, and that psychologists had underestimated the role of environmental factors. If true, this clearly has major implications well beyond psychology – for example, for debates about selection for secondary schooling. It is interesting even today to look at the debates between politicians of different hue, depending on whether they see crime as primarily caused by environmental factors, or by the innate criminality of the individual. Depending on which one is thought to be the more correct, very different social policy responses would be suggested.\nBehaviourism takes a deterministic stance, largely (or entirely) denying possibilities of human agency. Humans aren't seen as having the capacity for exerting conscious choice, but either react to stimuli or emit behaviour according to how they have been conditioned. A simple early study of classical conditioning involved Pavlov's famous work with dogs, who were trained to salivate on hearing a bell, sounded at the times they were fed. Eventually they would salivate at the sound of the bell alone, even without the presence of actual food. Humans may have much more complex 'contingencies of reinforcement' (and other types of conditioning, such as operant conditioning, where reinforcement is only given if the organism produces a specific response), but were seen by behaviourists as essentially similar in that they could be conditioned to react to stimuli (or emit behaviour). \nBehaviourism can be defined in two primary ways: • The weak definition, or methodological behaviourism, simply says the best strategy pragmatically for psychology as a discipline is to confine study to observable events: external behaviours. This approach doesn't necessarily deny that mental events are real, just that they can't be successfully studied scientifically. • The strong definition, or radical behaviourism, goes further, in actually rejecting the very concept of mental events. For example, Watson argued that thinking is just silent speech, i.e. not a private, internal process, but a behaviour that could be observed in principle (if the observer could pick up the very soft speech the thinker says to him or her self). Consciousness is seen as either just a brain by-product, with no causal effect on behaviour, or even completely non-existent. This approach to behaviourism originated with Watson, and was subsequently adopted and modified by Skinner. Some of the consequences of a strict, radical behaviourist viewpoint (such as the lack of conscious choice) have been explored by Skinner in his novel Walden Two. Although such a viewpoint has a limited following among contemporary psychologists, the pragmatic emphasis of methodological behaviourism still carries quite a strong resonance for many experimental psychologists, with externally-observable actions seen as central to psychological research, even if interpreted within a quite different theoretical context to that of behaviourism.
Learning
Learning. Although learning is usually defined in terms such as 'acquiring knowledge', psychology often makes use of a much more general way of defining this concept. Learning is seen as the process of acquiring changes in behaviour, knowledge, or any other type of understanding as a result of experience. To count as 'learning', these changes must be relatively stable and long-term. There are obvious links here with MEMORY, as the resulting behavioural or conceptual changes must be stored in some way in long-term memory.
During his PhD studies, Skinner put his early inventiveness to good use, building and refining the ' Skinner box' to provide a controlled environment for the study of learning using rats.
Burrhus Frederick Skinner was born in 1904 in Pennsylvania, USA. He completed his BA (in English lit erature) in 1926 and his PhD in 1931 from Harvard. He died in Massachusetts in 1990.
This was in distinction to the type of classical conditioning studied by Pavlov. Skinner at first tr ied to fit the notion of 'stimulus-response' (S-R) to his results and to develop associated theories. However, he found that this approach was not very productive and he abandoned it in favour of a largely non-theoretical and purely objective observation of behaviour.
Written by: Member of the Course Team
Skinner's first 23 years of life were full of 'haphazard passions with little overall plan'. Such pa ssions included building various inventions (including a steam cannon and a system of pulleys and strings to help him remember to hang up pyjamas.
The invention of the Skinner box permitted an enormous saving in time and effort: a number of animal s could be run in parallel with relatively little effort by the psychologist. His invention of a cumulative recorder to work alongside the Skinner box meant that the apparatus could be essentially free-running, the psychologist returning after a session to find the records.
Skinner's interest in applying his work to the design of societies was expressed in his novel Walden Two (1948) and in Beyond Freedom and Dignity (1971), both of which received much attention (and in some cases considerable criticism for their espousing of behaviorist tenets).
After completing his studies in English literature, in 1926 Skinner embarked on a career as a writer (which lasted one year) before beginning his graduate studies in psychology at Harvard.
Skinner's own version of radical behaviourism differed significantly from the traditional stimulus-r esponse version promoted by Watson and others. The focus of Skinner's work was very much on instrumental conditioning and in particular the special class termed 'operant conditioning'.
Skinner's interest in language culminated in the publication of Verbal Behaviour (1957). Noam Chomsk y's savaging of this book is often highlighted as a critical point in the shift of psychology from a behaviourist to a predominantly cognitive paradigm.
Top